Sunday, April 23, 2006

THE BIRTHING PAINS OF THE MARVELLOUS

I grant you that the morality Surrealism aims at promoting is still in its intuitive phase. It’s quite certain that for the famous “Each man according to his abilities,” “his works,” or “his needs” (materially speaking), not only Surrealism but all poetry worthy of the name has substituted an “Each man according to his desires.” […] In return for abolishing the “verboten” in every tongue, I have no doubt that the most extreme, and even most antisocial, points of desire would soon be absorbed.
(André Breton 1948)

The Unconscious is not a happy place; desire does not always bring joy. To anyone who has ever fallen in love, experienced violence, or simply been woken by a nightmare – that is, to everyone – these truths must be so obvious as to seem not worth stating.

The world against which we struggle is not just the ‘exterior’ world, but also the ‘interior’ world. Insofar as Surrealism seeks to bring these two worlds into communication, it will bring forth not just the beautiful Marvellous which we seek but also, inevitably, the reality we repudiate: the painful, the terrible, the horrific and the repulsive. The extent to which the history of the international Surrealist movement has been marked by acrimony, conflict and pain is testament to Surrealism’s propensity to call forth these monsters. They arise from the Unconscious not only in the sense of the Unconscious of individuals, but also from the Unconscious as an intersubjective force that operates between as well as within us. Collective dreaming can produce nightmares no less horrific than individual dreaming.

Such nightmares demand to be taken seriously as an essential aspect of Surrealism’s pre-figurative nature, just like the Surreality Principle itself. In living by Surrealist ideals we are striving paradoxically to act in harmony with the principles of a reality which does not yet exist but which we ourselves are trying to bring about: “Surreality – a relation in which all notions are merged together – […] the common horizon of religions, magic, poetry, intoxications, and of all life that is lowly – that trembling honeysuckle you deem sufficient to populate the sky with for us” (Louis Aragon 1924).

According to Freud, nightmares are the dreams which bear most clearly the marks of the conflict between the Pleasure Principle and the Reality Principle. Mutual anger and pain among Surrealist comrades bear the marks of the conflict between the Reality Principle of the world as it is and the Surreality Principle of the world as it will be: they are negative signs of the Marvellous, indentations or reverse impressions of the Surreality Principle. The nightmares we live through can guide us no less surely towards our revolutionary goals than our lovelier dreams of the Marvellous, but we must be prepared to regard them without flinching, without evading them or retreating to the comforts of narcissism, without losing courage or taking the easy route of either self-defence or self-blame.

By paying attention to our collective nightmares we can open a path by which those aspects of eroticism which are feared, rejected or abhorred may ultimately become transubstantiated, may stand revealed as a form of the Marvellous which can only be recognised by a fantastic leap of Surrealist Imagination – a leap begun in fear and rage, and ended in love and wonder.

***

The morning after I drafted my first notes on this posting – several months ago now – my close friend Stephen told me that he had dreamt about me that night. In his dream I had told him: “To make sense of a dream you have to make a circle with a monster at one end and an eye at the other. If you run away from the monster, the eye will tell you about your dream.”

Surely this reveals the true meaning of our dream-wars: an eye for an eye to reveal the truth of desire?

Thursday, April 20, 2006

THE SURREALITY PRINCIPLE

Surrealism has sometimes been accused – especially by those who, either deliberately or through ignorance, actively misrepresent it – of being a kind of escapism, immersed in a pursuit of fantasies and pleasures which is at best a retreat from reality, and at worst complicit with the hedonism of consumer society. These accusations are risibly false, and yet the ease with which they are made should give us pause. If the place of pleasure in Surrealist praxis appears so childishly simplistic to others, if Surrealist pleasure seems so inadequate to social reality, how are Surrealists to correct such views? Could it be, perhaps, that we Surrealists ourselves have conceived these issues in too simplistic a way? What is the place of pleasure in Surrealism?

One powerful strand of Surrealist thought, developed over several decades, has seen the task of Surrealism as the liberation of the Pleasure Principle from the Reality Principle, where the former is identified with unconscious desires and the latter with the repressive social and political order. It has been argued, for example, that the Pleasure Principle embodies a ‘will to authentic human integrity’; that the Reality Principle stands for the ‘egoistical irresponsibility’ of capitalism and its ecological destructiveness; that these two principles are as implacably opposed to each other as liberty is to repression; and that Surrealism is the demand that ‘the reality principle gives up its throne to the pleasure principle’ (Bruno Solarik, ‘The Walking Abyss’). Influential and inspiring as this argument has been, both politically and imaginatively, I do not follow it. I consider it mistaken in its characterisation of the relationship between the Pleasure Principle and the Reality Principle, and hence mistaken in its conception of the tasks of contemporary Surrealism.

As it has been conceived by many Surrealists, this pleasure/reality dichotomy (Pleasure Principle = authentic integrity and freedom, i.e. good, Reality Principle = repression and irresponsibility, i.e. bad) is at once too clear-cut and too static. In a word, it is simplistic. It assumes that the Pleasure Principle, in all its supposed infantile and aboriginal authenticity, pre-exists the Reality Principle of social conformity, and moreover that it does so in a fully formed state which is then simply repressed by the Reality Principle. Thus the Pleasure Principle is implicitly ascribed a ‘natural’ status which frames it within another dichotomy, that between nature and civilisation; and that dichotomy too is presented as a static and implacable opposition, where nature is equated with goodness and authenticity. This conception of the Pleasure Principle has often been presented as the theoretical basis of the Surrealist rage against what today passes for ‘civilisation’ world-wide. I share the rage, but I reject the theorisation, for the following reasons:

  1. I have argued elsewhere (Two Extracts from a Prolegomenon to a Surrealist Manifesto of Eroticism, a.k.a. the first SLAG manifesto) that desire and pleasure are neither ‘natural’ nor ‘originary’, and so I will not rehearse that argument at length here. Suffice it to say that in my view the Pleasure Principle is not a pre-given or natural paradise lost to which we can return by simply overthrowing ‘reality’. This is not least because the infantile pleasures at stake in the Pleasure Principle, from feeding to excretion to physical caresses, are themselves firmly embedded in social reality (the sexual division of labour, the relative material poverty of the child’s carers, variability in family forms which are not always – and certainly not preferably – Oedipal, etc. etc.). Moreover it must not be forgotten that the Reality Principle is no less a part of the Unconscious than the Pleasure Principle and that the latter cannot therefore claim a monopoly on ‘unconscious desires’. The ‘reality’ against which Surrealists struggle is not just the ‘exterior reality’ of capitalism, patriarchy, racism and environmental catastrophe, but also the ‘interior reality’ of egotism, Oedipality and the super-ego. This is precisely why the Surrealist revolution is psychical as well as material – because psychical reality and material reality are inextricably intertwined. Now as always we come back to Breton’s celebrated dictum: ‘“Transform the world,” Marx said; “change life,” Rimbaud said. These two watchwords are one for us.’ When we have changed the Reality Principle, the Pleasure Principle will also change, and vice versa: an eroticism which is truly free, like a civilisation which is truly free, will have been transfigured beyond recognition.
  2. It hardly needs restating that Surrealism since its first wave of activity has been concerned to seek the dialectical vanishing point between contradictions. This applies not just to the apparent contradiction between dreams and ‘reality’ but also, paradoxically, between freedom and necessity, as encapsulated in the supremely Surrealist understanding of the necessity of freedom. Moreover the positing of such contradictions as ‘mutually exclusive’ rests on an identitarian logic which is alien to Surrealist thought. Therefore our first impulse when faced with any apparent dichotomy, such as that between ‘pleasure’ and ‘reality’, should not be simplistically to align ourselves with one side or the other, but rather to seek the vanishing point between them by bringing them into dialectical play. In this case, the dialectical play between the Pleasure Principle and the Reality Principle brings forth a new term which embodies the necessity of freedom: the SURREALITY PRINCIPLE.
At the vanishing point between freedom and necessity lies the necessity of freedom. At the vanishing point between exterior reality and interior reality lies Surreality. And at the vanishing point between the Pleasure Principle and the Reality Principle lies the Surreality Principle. Surrealism’s task is to put the Surreality Principle into practice.

This is a paradox: to put the Surreality Principle into practice requires the changing of life and the transformation of the world; but life can only be changed and the world can only be transformed by acting in accordance with the Surreality Principle. In this respect it embodies the Surrealism’s essentially pre-figurative nature: we are striving to follow the principles of a reality which does not yet exist, but which we ourselves are trying to bring about precisely by following its principles.

This is not a question of rejecting the Reality Principle, or of setting up a romanticised version of the Pleasure Principle into which the requirements of thoughtful activity or physical survival, either for the individual or for the collective, somehow do not intrude. But whereas the Reality Principle represses the Imagination in accordance with the demands of accepted social reality, the Surreality Principle demands the abolition of accepted social reality in accordance with the demands of the Surrealist Imagination.

‘Surreality will reside in reality itself and will be neither superior nor exterior to it. And conversely, because the container shall also be the contained. […] I resist with all my strength the temptations which […] might have the immediate tendency to withdraw thought from life as well as place life under the aegis of thought’ (André Breton 1928). The Surreality Principle refuses neither civilisation nor the exercise of Reason. It demands the magical thinking of Surreason in the revolutionary pursuit of new and wholly beautiful forms of civilisation. When dreams, eroticism, chance, poetry, love and freedom are the foundation stones of all activity – only then will the word ‘civilisation’ have any meaning.